William James (1842-1910), a towering figure in American thought, was primarily a psychologist who made profound contributions to philosophy, particularly through his doctrines of “radical empiricism” and “pragmatism.”
As the recognized leader of American philosophy in his later life, James’s work was characterized by a unique blend of scientific inquiry and deep religious interest. His study of medicine led him to psychology, culminating in his highly influential book on the subject, but it was his philosophical explorations into the nature of experience, truth, and belief that left an indelible mark.
James’s doctrine of radical empiricism, first articulated in his 1904 essay “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?”, challenged the long-held philosophical assumption of a fundamental subject-object dualism. He argued that “consciousness” is not a separate entity or “thing,” but rather a name for a function that our thoughts perform.
For James, there is only one “primal stuff” or material from which everything in the world is composed: “pure experience.” Knowing, he asserted, is a particular kind of relation between two portions of pure experience, with the subject-object relation being derivative. A given, undivided portion of experience can function as a knower in one context and as something known in another, effectively abolishing the traditional distinction between mind and matter as two different kinds of “stuff.”
💡 Pragmatism: Truth as What ‘Works’ for Life
James is perhaps best known as one of the three protagonists of pragmatism, a theory that redefines “truth.” For James, an idea becomes “true” insofar as it helps us establish satisfactory relations with other parts of our experience. As he put it, “An idea is ‘true’ so long as to believe it is profitable to our lives.”
Truth, in this view, is not a static, eternal property that ideas possess, but rather something that happens to an idea; it is made true by events. This pragmatic definition implies that “the ‘true’ is only the expedient in the way of our thinking… in the long run and on the whole of course.” This means our obligation to seek truth is part of our broader obligation to do what is profitable for our lives.
He famously stated, “If the hypothesis of God works satisfactorily in the widest sense of the word, it is true.”
🙏 The ‘Will to Believe’: Justifying Faith in Uncertainty
James’s “will to believe” doctrine, articulated in his 1896 essay, argues that in situations where theoretical grounds for a decision are inadequate, we are often compelled to make choices. In such cases, he argued, we have a right to adopt a believing attitude, even if our “merely logical intellect may not have been coerced.”
He contended that the moral duty of veracity involves two coequal precepts: “believe truth” and “shun error.” The skeptic, by overly emphasizing the latter, risks missing out on important truths. For James, if believing a hypothesis yields useful consequences for life, then it is “true.”
This radical redefinition of truth, while controversial and criticized for its potential to justify any belief with positive effects, aimed to provide a philosophical justification for religious faith in an age of skepticism.
James’s philosophy, an attempt to build a superstructure of belief upon a foundation of empiricism, ultimately sought to reconcile the demands of human experience and moral aspiration with the limitations of purely intellectual knowledge, making him a profoundly influential voice in the development of American thought.
Source: Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy. Simon and Schuster, 1945.
More Topics
- John Dewey: Instrumentalism and the Evolution of Truth
- The Utilitarians: Can Happiness Be Quantified and Legislated?
- Karl Marx: The Philosopher of History, Class, and Revolution
- Bergson: The Philosopher of Life, Intuition, and Creative Evolution
- Locke’s Theory of Knowledge: How Did Empiricism Challenge Innate Ideas?
- Locke’s Political Philosophy: How Did He Justify Government by Consent?
- Schopenhauer: The Philosopher of Will, Suffering, and Pessimism